Sandra Day O'Connor
Mr. Vice Chancellor and Lord Chief Justice, and my lord millet and Sir David and Lady Williams, Professor Smith and distinguished guests, friends of Cambridge.
It is my great honour and pleasure to deliver the inaugural Sir
David Williams Lecture. Sir David is among the most distinguished
members of the legal academy not only in this country, but around
the world. His teaching career began at the University of
Nottingham, after which he taught at the University that, I am
told, is known affectionately in these parts as "the other place." Sir
David then joined the Law Faculty at Cambridge, later serving as
the Rouse Ball Professor of English Law and President of Wolfson
College. Sir David has been a path-breaker in the fields of
constitutional and administrative law. His books, "Not in the
Public Interest: The Problem of Security in Democracy", and
"Keeping the Peace: The Police and Public Order", are landmarks
in his fields and, I suspect, will be for a long time to come.
Sir David's impact, however, is not confined to the life of the
mind, but extends also to the world of public affairs. While
enhancing our understanding of democracy, he has demonstrated a
passionate concern for the quality of life in this democracy through
his public service. He has served on the Royal Commission on
Environmental Pollution, the Council of Tribunals, the Clean Air
Council, and a number of other bodies whose work is significant.
Sir David has also excelled as a leader of this University. Not only
did he serve as Vice Chancellor of Cambridge, he did such a good
job that his term was extended from two to seven years.
It is a privilege to be able to celebrate Sir David's achievements
and his indelible mark on learning and the law. It is an even
greater privilege to partake of the very first time that Sir David will
be honoured through this Lecture Series. The Book of Proverbs
tells us that "a good name is rather to be chosen than great
riches".' If that truth applies also to an event, I am certain that the
Sir David Williams Lecture Series will live long and will prosper.
* I would like to thank my law clerk, Stanley Panikowski, for his assistance in
preparing this speech.
1 Proverbs 22:1.
I am also proud to say that Sir David and I have a few things
in common. Each of us studied law in the great State of California:
Sir David received an LL.M. from the University of California at
Berkeley, and I received my J.D. from neighbouring Stanford. I
have also had the pleasure of participating with Sir David in the
Anglo-American Legal Exchange. He and I share a keen interest in
Transatlantic dialogue between the legal communities of our two
countries, which can enrich each other in so many ways. Perhaps
most coincidentally, Sir David and I share the same year of birth.
Speaking of notable years, we are currently in the midst of one.
As most people celebrated the putative eve of the new millennium
on 31 December 1999, a few sticklers for detail defiantly refused to
recognise an event that would not technically occur for another full
year. They studiously observed that the first year of any decade,
century, or millennium could begin only in a year ending in "1." If
any of you happened to be among those steadfast guardians of
epochal purity, I ask for no confession. All I ask is that, as one
who gladly celebrated the "counterfeit" turn of the millennium, I
not be estopped from claiming the privilege of speaking with you
now during the "real" first year of the new millennium.
Imagine the following scene at the turn of the next century
(whenever you think that precise event will occur): Four
businesspeople from around the globe share a table in an airport
café before dispersing to their respective homelands to celebrate New Year's Eve. The conversation soon turns to predictions of how
each of their countries will fare in the century to come. An
American venture capitalist, a Japanese entrepreneur, and a
Brazilian executive offer their partly sunny forecasts in turn. The
Englishman is the last to weigh in. When asked his thoughts on the
future of the United Kingdom, he replies, "I think it's quite a fine
idea. Perhaps somebody ought to try it again one of these days."
The possibility that, a hundred years hence, the United
Kingdom will exist only in theory may well be exaggerated. To
some, however, the only exaggeration may be the notion that it will
take that long. It is much too early to tell the long-term effects of
recent constitutional changes in the United Kingdom. What is clear
is that these changes are momentous.
Scholars have chronicled the twin late twentieth century
developments that have resulted in a United Kingdom that is being
"pulled in both directions."2
2 See, e.g., Michael H. Lee, "Revolution, Evolution, Devolution: Confusion?" (2000) 23 Suffolk
Transnat'l L. Rev. 465; Michael Burgess, "Constitutional Change in the United Kingdom: New
Model or Mere Respray?" (1999) 40 S. Tex. L. Rev. 715; Robert Hazell, "Westminster:
Squeezed From Above and Below", in Robert Hazell (ed.), Constitutional Futures: A History, of
the Next Ten Years (1999).
On the one hand, devolution has
effected an unprecedented delegation of power to elected bodies in
Scotland and Wales. New devolved institutions are also in place in Northern Ireland. There have been calls for greater devolution of
power to regions within England, reinforcement of the
constitutional status of local governments, and even whispers for
the creation of an English Parliament. At the same time, UK
membership in the European Union is exerting upward force on
powers traditionally exercised by Parliament alone. Punctuating the
complexity of these changes is the fact that the upward pressure of
European integration may increase the downward pressure of
devolution through the principle of subsidiarity and the
enforcement of EU law. One of the many important uncertainties
in the midst of this flux is the role that courts will play in
interpreting and enforcing these new arrangements.
If the changes underway in the United Kingdom are to be
measured (so far) in metres, then the magnitude of recent events
concerning the balance of power among the different levels of
government in the United States is more in the way of centimetres.
And rather than encountering new frontiers, the latest movement of
the dial in the United States has mostly been toward the
restoration of a balance that obtained not too long ago.
Nonetheless, federalism in America has been the subject of an
increasingly vigorous debate in recent years. At the heart of this
controversy has been the role of courts in interpreting and
enforcing the structural guarantees of our Constitution. One
American scholar, in speaking of federalism, has observed that
"perhaps no other concept, save judicial review, has stirred more
controversy".3 If this is so, then it should surprise no one that the
combination of the two excites great passions in my country.
These preliminary observations on the states (no pun intended)
of affairs in our two countries bring me to the thesis of today's
lecture. Each of our countries is deeply engaged in a debate
concerning the proper allocation of power among various levels of
government at the dawn of this new millennium. In each case,
however, the diffusion of power proceeds from a different premise.
In the United States, power originally resided with the people or
in the States and was ceded upward to a national government of
limited authority. In the United Kingdom, power is being
devolved from the sovereign Parliament of a unitary state to
national assemblies, and possibly to other regional actors. These
different premises have produced different historical trajectories
and different contemporary challenges.
3 Kermit L. Hall, "Introduction", in Kermit L. Hall (ed.) Federalism. A Nation of States (1987),
p. xi.
Yet federalism and
devolution in our respective countries also reflect many of the
same values and thus present many of the same opportunities.
Each of our countries, accordingly, has something to learn from
the other.
DEVOLUTION IN THE UNITED KINGDOM
The roots of the present devolution in the United Kingdom lie first
in the making of the United Kingdom itself.' The United
Kingdom's "coming to be" was clearly the product of an evolution,
not a revolution. While the contours of an English state had taken
shape by the middle of the tenth century, England's precise date of
birth is unknown.5 (If only the rest of us could shroud our ages in
such obscurity!) Wales, Scotland, and Northern Ireland became part
of today's United Kingdom through events that unfolded over
many centuries.6
The familiar principle of parliamentary sovereignty has long
animated the governance of this unitary state. Dicey famously
summarised the doctrine in this way: "The principle of
parliamentary sovereignty means neither more nor less than this,
namely, that Parliament . . . has, under the English constitution, the
right to make or unmake any law whatever; and, further, that no
person or body is recognised by the law of England as having a
right to override or set aside the legislation of Parliament."7 While
institutions facilitating local control of varying forms and degrees
have also been part of this multinational Kingdom,8 rule has been
unmistakably from the centre.
Calls for greater self-government by the nations comprising the
United Kingdom are by no means an innovation of the late
twentieth century. For example, the question of Irish Home Rule
that gripped the United Kingdom during the late nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries naturally stirred sentiment for greater
autonomy elsewhere.9 In 1973, the Royal Commission on the
Constitution issued the Kilbrandon Report, which recommended
the establishment of elected assemblies in Scotland and Wales."
4 See, e.g., Vernon Bogdanor, Devolution in the United Kingdom (1999), p. 3; Burgess, note 2
above, at pp. 716-719.
5 Bogdanor, note 4 above, at p. 5.
6 See generally ibid. at pp. 3-18.
7 A.V. Dicey, Law of the Constitution (E.C.S. Wade ed., 10th ed. 1959), pp. 39-40.
8 See generally Martin Loughlin, "Restructuring of Central-Local Government Relations", in
Jeffrey .Jowell & Dawn Oliver (eds.), The Changing Constitution, 4th ed., (2000), pp. 137-164.
9 See Bogdanor, note 4 above, at pp. 44-45.
10 Helin Rees, "Awakening the Welsh Dragon: Will the Creation of the National Assembly for
Wales Make A Significant Difference to the Constitutional Arrangements Between England
and Wales?" (2000) 23 Suffolk Transnat'l L. Rev. 459, 462-463.
A
quarter-century after the publication of the Kilbrandon report, Acts
of Parliament authorised elected national assemblies in Scotland,
Wales, and Northern Ireland."
One of the most salient features of the present devolution is that
different institutions have been ordained and different powers
devolved in each territory. For example, the Scottish Parliament is a
true legislative body with an extensive list of devolved powers.12 It
can pass primary legislation within its areas of competence, has
some power to vary taxes, and has its own representative office in
Brussels.13 In contrast to the devolution model proposed in the
1970s, the powers reserved to the Westminster Parliament are
enumerated.14 Like Scotland, Northern Ireland is experiencing both
legislative and executive devolution, but with wrinkles like powersharing
because of its situation as a divided society.15 The order of
the day in Wales, on the other hand, is simply executive
devolution.16 The Welsh Assembly has the power to make
secondary, but not primary, legislation.17 Its areas of competence
are more limited than those of the Scottish Parliament.18 The Welsh
Assembly operates chiefly through a cabinet, and is much more
dependent on Westminster and Whitehall than the other
assemblies.19
In all cases, the assemblies are subordinate to the Westminster
Parliament, which retains supremacy throughout the entire United
Kingdom.20 Many scholars have pointed out that devolution thus
rests on two seemingly conflicting principles: parliamentary
sovereignty and domestic self-government.21 But parliamentary
sovereignty is not, in theory, incompatible with the exercise of some
local control. The theoretical reconciliation of these principles lies
in the idea that the authority exercised at levels below the central
government ultimately derives from and depends on the will of
Parliament.
The recent changes are consistent with this constitutional theory,
but the fit between the theory and the new constitutional reality is
a far different question.
11 See Scotland Act 1998; Government of Wales Act 1998; Northern Ireland Act 1998.
12 Burgess, note above 2, at pp. 722-723.
13 Ibid. at p. 723; Geoffrey Clark, "Scottish Devolution and the European Union" [1999] Pub.
Law 505, 519-522.
14 Bogdanor, note 4 above, at p. 204.
15 Ibid. at pp. 105-109; Winston Roddick, "Devolution-The United Kingdom and the New
Wales" (2000) 23 Suffolk Transnat'l L. Rev., 477, 482-483; Burgess, note 2 above, at pp. 726-
728.
16 Vernon Bogdanor, "Devolution and the British Constitution", in David Butler et al. (eds.),
The Law. Politics, and the Constitution (1999), pp. 71-72.
17 Roddick, note 15 above, at p. 482.
18 Burgess, note 2 above, at p. 724.
19 Ibid. at pp. 724-725.
20 Bogdanor, note 4 above, at p. 3.
21 See, e.g., Bogdanor, note 16 above, at p. 55; Hazell, note 2 above, at p. I II.
Devolution is technically a revocable
licence, not a conveyance in fee simple.22 But what is legally
permissible may be politically impossible. Many scholars have
asserted that it is unlikely that Westminster would recall devolved
powers without the consent of the national assembly at issue.23
Indeed, such an attempt might well be considered
"unconstitutional" in the British sense.
We all know what parliamentary sovereignty meant to Dicey.
But what will Westminster's sovereignty now mean in Edinburgh?
What will it mean in Cardiff, in Belfast? If devolution extends to
the English regions, will it also have a new meaning in Yorkshire?
Will parliamentary sovereignty still cloak the United Kingdom? If
so, will it be a coat of many colours? Or will it simply be like the
Emperor's new clothes?
Given my line of work, one of the issues surrounding devolution
that I find to be especially compelling is the role of courts. The
source, status, and character of judicial review in the United
Kingdom differ in many ways from the features of judicial review
in the United States. Parliamentary sovereignty and the absence of
out-and-out constitutional adjudication stand on one side of the
Atlantic, while Article Ill and Marbury v. Madison [24] reside on the
opposite shore. In practice, of course, the gap has narrowed in
recent decades due to developments in the judicial role in the
United Kingdom. Recent constitutional changes in the United
Kingdom raise the questions what effect the courts will have on
devolution and, just as important, what effect devolution will have
on the role of courts.
The devolution Acts expressly assign the UK courts a role in
determining the limits of devolution and the powers of the devolved
institutions.25 At a broad level, this role is a familiar one for UK
courts. The question whether a devolved body has acted within the
limits of its devolved powers dovetails nicely with the type of ultra
vires review to which UK courts are accustomed.26 Likewise, at
least in the cases of Scotland and Northern Ireland, the judicial
review of actions by the UK executive to ensure that they are
within the powers that Parliament has reserved to Westminster does
not require new wineskins. As Lord Falconer put it, "These sorts
22 See Abimbola A. Olowofoycku, "Devolution: Conceptual and Implementational Problems"
(2000) 29 Anglo-Am. L. Rev. 133, 161-162.
23 See, e.g., Bogdanor, note 16 above, at p. 61; lan Leigh, Law', Politics, and Local Democracy
(2000), pp. 27-28; Dawn Oliver & Gavin Drewry, "The law and Parliament", in Dawn Oliver
& Gavin Drewry (eds.) The Law and Parliament (1998) p. 2; but see Olowofoyeku, note 22
above, at p. 162.
24 1 Cranch 137 (1803).
25 Lord Falconer of Thoroton Q.C., "The Role of the Courts in the Devolution and Human
Rights Arrangements" (1999) 21 Liverpool L. Rev. 1, 1.
26 See ibid. at pp. 10, 14.
of cases are ones where the court will be adjudicating in a way in
which they are very experienced-deciding as a matter of law what
the competence of a particular body is."27
But while the exercise may be familiar, the precise subject
matter may present some uncharted territory. Devolution will
involve the courts more in the business of drawing vertical
institutional boundaries. It remains to be seen how extensive this
role will be, and what patterns will emerge from the exercise of this
adjudicative authority. For example, in the case of Scotland, will
the courts construe more broadly the devolved powers or the
reserved powers? In Wales, will the courts be swift or slow to find
that executive action exceeds the limits of Westminster's primary
legislation? And how will the courts approach national assembly
action in areas that intermingle both devolved and reserved powers?
Just as Parliament will retain in theory the power to alter or
rescind the devolution arrangements at any time, it can overrule
any judicial resolution of a devolution issue that is not to its
liking.28 Indeed, the very role of the courts in devolution will
remain subject to change at parliamentary will. In other words,
wherever the courts draw vertical institutional boundaries,
Westminster will still hold the supreme legislative rubber.
But there is bound to be a gap between constitutional theory
and constitutional practice. The manner in which UK courts have
construed primary legislation to vindicate fundamental
constitutional rights has received much attention in recent
decades.29 While technically abiding within the confines of statutory
construction, these decisions sometimes have the flavour of fullfledged
constitutional review. Now that Parliament has delegated
substantial powers to the national assemblies, it will be interesting
to see whether the courts treat these powers in essence as
permanently transferred or simply on indefinite loan.
FEDERALISM IN THE UNITED STATES
I will now travel across the ocean and back in time to trace the
outlines of federalism in the United States. The character of
American federalism is also deeply rooted in the way our nation
was forged. The Framers engaged in extensive debate concerning
the appropriate allocation of power between the States and the
national government. If the Constitutional Convention had taken
27 Ibid. at p. 14.
28 Ibid. at p. 7.
29 See, e.g., ibid. at p. 9; Paul Craig, "Constitutionalism, Regulation and Review", in
Constitutional Futures, above note 2, at p. 83; Jeffrey Jowell, "Of Vires and Vacuums" [1999]
Pub. Law 448, 457-458.
place over a Wimbledon fortnight, there is little doubt that
questions of federalism would have held Centre Court. The Framers
were gripped by competing concerns. On the one hand, the
Framers "were suspicious of every form of all-powerful central
authority",30 which they viewed as inimical to individual liberty. On
tile other hand, the Articles of Confederation had proven to be too
weak a tonic for the achievement of national goals because the
central government was entirely dependent on the cooperation of
State legislatures.
State sovereignty was at the heart of the dilemma. While the
Framers were committed to the preservation of state sovereignty, it
could not be the insuperable obstacle to coordinated action that it
had proven to be under the confederation. The Framers were thus
confronted with the challenge of navigating between the Scylla of
excessively concentrated power and the Charybdis of disunity.
The Framers hammered out a series of compromises, some of
which guaranteed an institutional role for the States in the
composition of the central government itself. For example, as a
result of the Connecticut Compromise, each State was afforded
equal representation in the Senate."31
But the Framers did not think it would be enough simply to
place State hands on the central tiller. The Framers instead
provided that the central government would be one of limited,
enumerated powers, with the States retaining those powers that
they did not delegate. At the same time, the Constitution forbade
the States from exercising certain powers that would rest in the
central government alone.32 These principles are the primary fulcrum on which the ultimate balance between state authority and
national power rests. The limitation of the central government's
authority is inherent in our constitutional design. The Tenth
Amendment, ratified in 1791, reinforces this design by stating that
famous "truism" 33: "The powers not delegated to the United States
by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved
to the States respectively, or to the people." The Framers thus
established dual spheres of sovereignty, allowing the central
government to act directly upon individuals in some fields of
activity while preserving the sovereignty of States acting within
their own territorial boundaries.
Today's central government certainly does not resemble the
limited enterprise that the Framers of our Constitution envisioned.
30 Justice John Harlan, "Thoughts at a Dedication: Keeping the Judicial Function in Balance'
(1963) 49 ABA. 943, 944.
31 US Const., art. I, 3, cl. I.
32 US Const., art. I, § 10.
33 United States v. Darby, 312 US 100, 124 (1941).
While some of the expansion is a result of formal constitutional
amendments, the country's response to technological and social
change accounts for the lion's share of the growth of central power.
The Framers could not have foreseen our world of technological
sophistication and mass communication. They could not have
known the Internet, the 747, or biotech corn any more than they
could have envisioned cable television, cloning, or the splitting of
the atom. Chiefly through Congress's exercise of its powers under
the Commerce and Spending Clauses,34 aided by broad judicial
interpretations, the sphere of federal activity has greatly expanded.
The ability to adapt to new circumstances within the same constitutional framework is indeed testimony to the wisdom of our
forebears. But while the Framers prudently designed a flexible
system, they did not adopt principles without limits. Nor did they
neglect to design institutions that would enforce those limits. Marbury v. Madison confirmed not only the power of judicial
review generally, but specifically the competence of courts to
enforce the constitutionally enshrined balance of power among the
different organs of government.35
Yet these first principles have come tinder increasing attack.
Some have encouraged the judiciary to effectively abdicate its role
as an "institutional border patrol" under the appealing label of
"the political safeguards of federalism". 3
1 Under this view,
enforcement of the federal-state balance should be left to the
political process, in which the Framers have already guaranteed a
role for the States.
In my view, both the "political" and the "judicial" safeguards of
federalism reinforce the federal-state balance.37 There is ample room
for political accommodation within the parameters of our system.
Just as the States do not regulate conduct within their borders to
the fullest permissible extent, Congress does not always legislate to
the limits of its constitutional authority. But the courts are
nonetheless obligated to remedy the transgression of constitutional
borders in the cases and controversies before them. In discharging
this function, the courts should strive to emulate a prudent umpire,
who allows the contestants to play hard between the lines but takes
swift and sure action when those lines are crossed. While
34 US Const., art. I, § 8, cl. 3; US Const., art. 1, § 8, cl. 1.
35 1 Cranch 137 (1803).
36 See, e.g., Jesse H. Choper, Judicial Reiview and the National Political Process: A Functional
Reconsideration of the Role of the Supreme Court (1980); Herbert Wechsler, "The Political
Safeguards of Federalism: The Role of the States in the Composition and Selection of the
National Government" (1954) 54 Colum. L. Rev. 543.
37 Cf. Garcia v. San Antonio Metro. Transit Auth., 469 US 528, 580-589 (1985) (O'Connor, J..
dissenting); see also John C. Yoo, "Judicial Review and Federalism" (1998) 22 Harv. J.L. &
Pub. Pol'y 197.
reasonable minds may differ as to where those lines are, line-drawing
is the essence of law.3" The difficulty of the task is no
cause to shrink from it. As my colleague Justice Kennedy has said,
"[T]he federal balance is too essential a part of our constitutional
structure and plays too vital a role in securing freedom for us to
admit inability to intervene when one or the other level of
Government has tipped the scales too far."3
9
Recent debates in the political arena in the United States over
such issues as welfare reform, energy policy, and the future of
health care testify to the ample latitude that the national and state
governments have to negotiate their respective spheres of action. It
is just as much the role of the courts not to intervene in the
legitimate machinations of the political process. But when a
particular action, whether a result of political compromise or
unilateral political will, violates the Constitution, judicial
intervention is warranted.
COMPARING DEVOLUTION IN THE UNITED KINGDOM WITH FEDERALISM IN AMERICA
This abbreviated discussion reveals several substantial differences
between devolution in the United Kingdom and federalism in the
United States. These and other differences have been of interest to
students and scholars of comparative law. Federalism represents a
true division of power, whereas devolution is simply a delegation.
While each of our countries is a Union, there are two spheres of
sovereignty in America, but a single realm in the United Kingdom. Our countries' names reflect this difference: both begin with
"United," but the second word is plural in one, singular in the
other. In the United States, the power of actors away from the
centre is a postulate. In the United Kingdom, it is a wholly
dependent proposition.
These facts, of course, represent much more than conceptual
footnotes to history. Rather, they influence the constitutional and
political realities of the vertical allocation of power in each country.
For example, residual state sovereignty in America means that, even
in an era where the exercise of national power is often the
instinctive norm rather than the deliberate exception, the federal
government is limited in the extent to which it can commandeer,
override, or displace the States.40 And despite the exponential
38 Cf. Irwin v. Gavit, 268 US 161, 168 (1925) ("Neither are we troubled by the question where to
draw the line. That is the question in pretty much everything worth arguing in the law.").
39 United States v. Lopez, 514 US 549, 578 (1995) (Kennedy, J., concurring).
40 See, e.g.. Printz v. United States, 521 US 898 (1997); Lopez, 514 US 549; New York v. United
States, 505 US 144 (1992).
increase in the pages of the United States Code since the New
Deal, the fact remains that the vast bulk of our law is state law. In
the United Kingdom, what Parliament hath devolved, it can taketh
away. And even if the political realities would make it very dificult
for Parliament to roll back significantly the present devolutionary
arrangements, the prospect of rescission is a part of the
constitutional and political backdrop against which the new
devolved institutions operate.
The territorial units that comprise the lower level of government
are defined on a different basis in each country. In the United
Kingdom, each of the units to which substantial power has been
devolved has a distinct national identity. In the United States,
though each State has its own ethnic mix and cultural flavours, the
lines are strictly geographical. The multinational, as opposed to
merely multiethnic, composition of the United Kingdom may create
centrifugal pressures to a degree not present in the United States.
Indeed, some see devolution as a halfway house on the road to full
independence. For example, a Scottish National Party spokesperson
recently said: "Rather than killing nationalism stone cold dead, we
see devolution as a stepping stone toward independence."'" Others,
however, view devolution as a "safety valve" for the release of
nationalist pressures to preserve the integrity of the Union. For
example, the UK Foreign Secretary said recently: "[B]y recognising
the United Kingdom's diversity, devolution has guaranteed its
future."42 While it may be a paradox to say that one can fasten a
Union by loosening the political ties that bind it, it is a paradox in
which many place great faith.
Further, devolution in the United Kingdom is asymmetrical,
while federalism in America is almost perfectly symmetrical.
Asymmetry in the United Kingdom is enabled by the fact that
power is flowing from the top down, and results from the interplay
of historical forces and present demand.
In the United States, asymmetry is practically unheard of (and
is likely even "unthought of"). In large part, symmetry of powers
among States results from the fact that state powers are not
enumerated and the only cession of power is upward. While there
may be asymmetry of influence in national affairs, each State
regulates within its own borders on equal terms. And even though
roughly 170 years separated the ratification of the Constitution by
the first State, Delaware, and the entry into the Union of the
41 Jason Beattie, "Devolution Helps the UK, says Cook" Scoisman, 20 April 2001, at p. II; see
also Bogdanor, note 4 above, at p. 296.
42 Beattie, note 44 above; See also Robert Hazell & Brendan O'Leary, "A Rolling Programme of
Devolution: Slippery Slope or Safeguard of the Union". in Constitutional Futures, note 2
above, at pp. 45-46; Bogdanor, note 4 above, at pp. 297-298.
fiftieth State, Hawaii, each State has entered on an equal footing
with the others.
While many extol the virtues of asymmetrical devolution as the
most logical response to the disparate situations of nations within
the United Kingdom, others believe that asymmetry makes the
present arrangements unsatisfactory and inherently unstable. 3 It
remains to be seen whether asymmetry remains the rule or a
pattern of convergence emerges. For example, will Wales look at
the Scottish Parliament and want the same legislative and tax-varying
powers for its own assembly?44 And if the Welsh keep up
with the Scots, will the Smiths then want to stay a step ahead of
the Joneses?
Another important dimension of the asymmetry question is the
status of England and the English regions. Many of the concerns
driving devolution, such as a perception of excessive centralisation
and remoteness from the decisions that affect everyday lives,45
apply to England as well. As a result, there have been calls for
greater devolution of power to regions within England.46
The role of courts in policing the borders between the different
levels of government is a matter of longer standing and greater
certainty in the United States than it is in the United Kingdom.
The political and judicial safeguards of federalism exist alongside
each other in the United States. In the United Kingdom, by
contrast, judicial protections are ultimately subject to political will,
and Pa